用户∶  密码∶    · 新用户注册 · 取回密码
您现在的位置: 首页>>研究生论坛>>外文资料库>>正文

Ethics(1912) Chapter 5. Results the Test of Right

时间:2012-03-07 18:33:07 点击:

核心提示:Chapter 5. Results the Test of Right and Wrong....

Chapter 5. Results the Test of Right and Wrong.

Inour last chapterwe began considering objections to one very fundamental principle, which is presupposed by the theory stated in the first two chapters梐 principle which may be summed up in the two propositions (1) that the question whether an action is right or wrong always depends upon itstotalconsequences, and (2) that if it is once right to prefer one set oftotalconsequences,A, to another set,B, it must always be right to prefer any set precisely similar toAto any set precisely similar toB. The objections to this principle, which we considered inthe last chapter, rested on certain views with regard to the meaning of the words搑ight?/Q> and揼ood.?/Q> But there remain several other quite independent objections, which may be urged against it even if we reject those views. That is to say, there are objections which may and would be urged against it by many people who accept both of the two propositions which I was trying to establish inthe last chapter, namely (1) that to call an action搑ight?/Q> or搘rong?/Q> is not the same thing as to say that any being whatever has towards it any mental attitude whatever; and (2) that if any given whole is once intrinsically good or bad, any whole precisely similar to it must always be intrinsically good or bad in precisely the same degree. And in the present chapter I wish briefly to consider what seem to me to be the most important of these remaining objections.(Ch. 5 ?1)

All of them are directed against the view that right and wrong do always depend upon an action抯actualconsequences or results. This may be denied for several different reasons; and I shall try to state fairly the chief among these reasons, and to point out why they do not seem to be conclusive.(Ch. 5 ?2)

In the first place, it may be said that, by laying down the principle that right and wrong depend upon consequences, we are doing away with the distinction between what is adutyand what is merelyexpedient; and between what iswrongand what is merelyinexpedient. People certainly do commonly make a distinction between duty and expediency. And it may be said that the very meaning of calling an action揺xpedient?/Q> is to say that it will produce the best consequences possible under the circumstances. If, therefore, we also say that an action is aduty, whenever and only when it produces the best possible consequences, it may seem that nothing is left to distinguish duty from expediency.(Ch. 5 ?3)

Now, as against this objection, it is important to point out, first of all, that, even if we admit that to call an action expedient is the same thing as to say that it produces the best possible consequences, our principle still does not compel us to hold that to call an action expedient isthe same thingas to call it a duty. All that it does compel us to hold is that whatever is expedient is alwaysalsoa duty, and that whatever is a duty is alwaysalsoexpedient. That is to say, itdoesmaintain that duty and expediencycoincide; but it doesnotmaintain that the meaning of the two words is the same. It is, indeed, quite plain, I think, that the meaning of the two words isnotthe same; for, if it were, then it would be a mere tautology to say that it is always our duty to do what will have the best possible consequences. Our theory does not, therefore, do away with the distinction between themeaningof the words揹uty?/Q> and揺xpediency?/Q>; it only maintains that both will always apply to the same actions.(Ch. 5 ?4)

But, no doubt, what is meant by many who urge this objection is to deny this. What they mean to say is not merely that to call an action expedient is a different thing from calling it a duty, but also that sometimes whatisexpedient iswrong, and whatisa duty is inexpedient. This is a view which is undoubtedly often held; people often speak as if there often were an actual conflict between duty and expediency. But many of the cases in which it would be commonly held that there is such a conflict may, I think, be explained by supposing that when we call an action揺xpedient?/Q> we do not always mean quite strictly that itstotalconsequences, taking absolutelyeverythinginto account, are the best possible. It is by no means clear that we do always mean this. We may, perhaps, sometimes mean merely that the action is expedient for some particular purpose; and sometimes that it is expedient in the interests of the agent, though not so on the whole. But if we only mean this, our theory, of course, doesnotcompel us to maintain that the expedientisalways a duty, and duty always an expedient. It only compels us to maintain this, if揺xpedient?/Q> be understood in the strictest and fullest sense, as meaning that, whenabsolutely allthe consequences are taken into account, they will be found to be the best possible. And if this be clearly understood, then most people, I think, will be reluctant to admit that it can ever be really inexpedient to do our duty, or that what is really and truly expedient, in this strict sense, can ever be wrong.(Ch. 5 ?5)

But, no doubt, some people may still maintain that it is or may be sometimes our duty to do actions which willnothave the best possible consequences, and sometimes also positively wrong, to do actions which will. And the chief reason why this is held is, I think, the following.(Ch. 5 ?6)

It is, in fact, very commonly held indeed that there are certain specific kinds of action which are absolutely always right, and others which are absolutely always wrong. Different people will, indeed, take different views as to exactly what kinds of action have this character. A rule which will be offered by one set of persons as a rule to which there is absolutely no exception will be rejected by others, as obviously admitting of exceptions; but these will generally, in their turn, maintain that some other rule, which they can mention, really has no exceptions. Thus there are enormous numbers of people who would agree thatsome rule or other(and generally more than one) oughtabsolutely alwaysto be obeyed; although probably there is not one single rule whichallthe persons who maintain this would agree upon. Thus, for instance, some people might maintain that murder (defined in some particular way) is an act which ought absolutelyneverto be committed; or that to actjustlyis a rule which ought absolutely always to be obeyed; and similarly it might be suggested with regard to many other kinds of actions, that they are actions, which it is eitheralwaysour duty, oralwayswrong to do.(Ch. 5 ?7)

But once we assert with regard to any rule of this kind that itis absolutely alwaysour duty to obey it, it is easy and natural to take one further step and to say that itwouldalways be our duty to obey it,whateverthe consequences might be. Of course, this further step does not necessarily and logically follow from the mere position that there are some kinds of action which ought,in fact, absolutely always to be done or avoided. For it is just possible that there are some kinds which do, as a matter of fact, absolutely always produce the best possible consequences, and other kinds which absolutely never do so. And there is a strong tendency among persons who hold the first position to hold that, as a matter of fact, this is the case: that right actions always do, as a matter of fact, produce the best possible results, and wrong actions never. Thus even those who would assent to the maxim that揓ustice should always be done, though the heavens should falls,?/Q> will generally be disposed to believe that justice never will, in fact, cause the heavens to fall, but will rather be always the best means of upholding them. And similarly those who say that搚ou should never do evil that good may come,?/Q> though their maxim seems to imply that goodmaysometimes come from doing wrong, would yet be very loth to admit that, by doing wrong, you ever wouldreallyproduce better consequenceson the wholethan if you had acted rightly instead. Or again, those who say搕hat the end will never justify the means,?/Q> though they certainly imply that certain ways of acting would be always wrong,whateveradvantages might be secured by them, yet, I think, would be inclined to deny that the advantages to be obtained by acting wrongly ever doreallyoutweigh those to be obtained by acting rightly, if we take into account absolutelyallthe consequences of each course.(Ch. 5 ?8)

Those, therefore, who hold that certain specific ways of acting are absolutely always right, and others absolutely always wrong, do, I think, generally hold that the former do also, as a matter of fact, absolutely always produce the best results, and the latter never. But, forthe reasons given at the beginning of Chapter III, it is, I think, very unlikely that this belief can be justified. The total results of an action always depend, not merely on the specific nature of the action, but on the circumstances in which it is done; and the circumstances vary so greatly that it is, in most cases, extremely unlikely that any particular kind of action willabsolutelyalways, in absolutely all circumstances, either produce or fail to produce the best possible results. For this reason, if we do take the view that right and wrong depend upon consequences, we must, I think, be prepared to doubt whether any particular kind of action whatever is absolutely always right or absolutely always wrong. For instance, however we define搈urder,?/Q> it is unlikely that absolutelynocase will ever occur in which it would be right to commit a murder; and, however we define搄ustice,?/Q> it is unlikely thatnocase will ever occur in which it would be right to do an injustice. No doubt it may be possible to define actions of which it is true that, in animmensemajority of cases, it is right or wrong to perform them; and perhapssomerules of this kind might be found to which there are reallynoexceptions. But in the case of most of the ordinary moral rules, it seems extremely unlikely that obedience to them willabsolutely alwaysproduce the best possible results. And most persons who realise this would, I think, be disposed to give up the view that they ought absolutelyalwaysto be obeyed. They would be content to accept them asgeneralrules, to which there are very few exceptions, without pretending that they are absolutely universal.(Ch. 5 ?9)

But, no doubt, there may be some persons who will hold, in the case of some particular rule or set of rules, that even if obedience to it does in some casesnotproduce the best possible consequences, yet we ought even in these cases to obey it. It may seem to them that they really do know certain rules, which oughtabsolutely alwaysto be obeyed,whateverthe consequences may be, and even, therefore, if the total consequences are not the best possible. They may, for instance, take quite seriously the assertion that justice ought to be done, even though the heavens should fall, as meaning that,howeverbad the consequences of doing an act of justice might in some circumstances be, yet it always would be our duty to do it. And such a view does necessarily contradict our principle; since, whether it be true or not that an act of injustice ever actually could in this world produce the best possible consequences, it is certainly possible toconceivecircumstances in which it would do so. I doubt whether those who believe in the absolute universality of certain moral rules do generally thus distinguish quite clearly between the question whether disobedience to the rule evercouldproduce the best possible consequences, and the question whether,ifit did, then disobedience would be wrong. They would generally be disposed to argue that it never reallycould. But some persons might perhaps hold that, even if it did, yet disobedience would be wrong. And if this view be quite clearly held, there is, so far as I can see, absolutely no way of refuting it except by appealing to the self-evidence of the principle that if weknewthat the effect of a given action really would be to make the world, as a whole,worsethan it would have been if we had acted differently, it certainly would be wrong for us to do that action. Those who say that certain rules oughtabsolutely alwaysto be obeyed,whateverthe consequences may be, are logically bound to deny this; for by saying?SPAN class=emphasis>whateverthe consequences may be,?/Q> they do imply?SPAN class=emphasis>even ifthe world as a whole were the worse because of our action.?/Q> It seems to me to be self-evident that knowingly to do an action which would make the world, on the whole, really and trulyworsethan if we had acted differently, must always be wrong. And if this be admitted, then it absolutely disposes of the view that there are any kinds of actions whatever, which itwouldalways be our duty to do or to avoid,whateverthe consequences might be.(Ch. 5 ?10)

For this reason it seems to me we must reject this particular objection to the view that right and wrong always depend upon consequences; namely, the objection that there are certainkindsof action which ought absolutely always and quite unconditionally to be done or avoided. But there still remain two other objections, which are so commonly held, that it is worth while to consider them.(Ch. 5 ?11)

The first is the objection that righ wrong depend neither upon the nature of the action, nor upon its consequences, but partly, or even entirely, upon themotiveormotivesfrom which it is done. By the view that it dependspartlyupon the motives, I mean the view that no action can bereallyright, unless it be done from some one motive or some one of a set of motives, which are supposed to be good; but that the being done from such a motive is not sufficient,by itself, to make an action right: that the action, if it is to be right, must alwaysalsoeither produce the best possible consequences, or be distinguished by some other characteristic. And this view, therefore, will not necessarily contradict our principle so far as it asserts that no action can be right,unlessit produces the best possible consequences: it only contradicts that part of it which asserts thateveryaction which does produce them is right. But the view has sometimes been held, I think, that right and wrong dependentirelyupon motives: that is to say, that not only is no action right,unlessit be done from a good motive, but also thatanyaction which is done from some one motive or some one of a set of motives is always right, whatever the consequences may be and whatever it may be like in other respects. And this view, of course, will contradict both parts of our principle; since it not only implies that an action, which produces the best possible consequences may be wrong, but also that an action may be right, in spite of failing to produce them.(Ch. 5 ?12)

In favour of both these views it may be urged that in our moral judgments we actually do, and ought to, take account of motives; and indeed that it marks a great advance in morality when men do begin to attach importance to motives and are not guided exclusively in their praise or blame, by the揺xternal?/Q> nature of the act done or by its consequences. And all this may be fully admitted. It is quite certain that when a man does an action which has bad consequences from a good motive, we do tend to judge him differently from a man who does a similar action from a bad one; and also that when a man does an action which has good consequences from a bad motive, we may nevertheless think badly of him for it. And it may be admitted that, in some cases at least, it is right and proper that a man抯 motives should thus influence our judgment. But the question is: Whatsortof moral judgment is it right and proper that they should influence? Should it influence our view as to whether the action in question is right or wrong? It seems very doubtful whether, as a rule, it actually does affect our judgment on this particular point, for we are quite accustomed to judge that a man sometimes actswronglyfrom the best of motives; and though we should admit that the good motive forms some excuse, and that the whole state of things is better than if he had done the same thing from a bad motive, it yet does not lead us to deny that the actioniswrong. There is, therefore, reason to think that the kind of moral judgments which a consideration of motives actuallydoesaffect do not consist of judgments as to whether the action done from the motive isrightorwrong; but are moral judgments ofsome different kind; and there is still more reason to think that it is only judgments of some different kind whichoughtto be influenced by it.(Ch. 5 ?13)

The fact is that judgments as to the rightness and wrongness of actions are by no means the only kind of moral judgments which we make; and it is, I think, solely because some of these other judgments are confused with judgments of right and wrong that the latter are ever held to depend upon the motive. There are three other kinds of judgments which are chiefly concerned in this case. In the first place it may be held that some motives areintrinsically goodand othersintrinsically bad; and though this is a view which is inconsistent with the theory of our first two chapters, it is not a view which we are at present concerned to dispute: for it is not at all inconsistent with the principle which we are at present considering梟amely, that right and wrong always depend solely upon consequences. If we held this view, we might still hold that a man may act wrongly from a good motive, and rightly from a bad one, and that the motive would make no difference whatever to the rightness or wrongness of the action. What it would make a difference to is the goodness or badness of the whole state of affairs: for, if we suppose the same action to be done in one case from a good motive and in the other from a bad one, then, so far as the consequences of the action are concerned, the goodness of the whole state of things will be the same, while the presence of the good motive will mean the presence of anadditionalgood in the one case which is absent in the other. For this reason alone, therefore, we might justify the view that motives are relevant tosomekinds of moral judgments, though not to judgments of right and wrong.(Ch. 5 ?14)

And there is yet another reason for this view, and this a reason which may be consistently held even by those who hold the theory of our first two chapters. It may be held, namely, that good motives have ageneraltendency to produce right conduct, though they do notalwaysdo so, and bad motives to produce wrong conduct; and this would be another reason which would justify us in regarding right actions done from a good motive differently from right actions done from a bad one. For though, in the case supposed, the bad motive would notactuallyhave led to wrong action, yet, if it is true that motives of that kind dogenerallylead to wrong action, we should be right in passing this judgment upon it; and judgments to the effect that a motive is of a kind which generally leads to wrong action are undoubtedly moral judgments of a sort, and an important sort, though they do not prove that every action done from such a motive is wrong.(Ch. 5 ?15)

And finally motives seem also to be relevant to a third kind of moral judgment of great importance梟amely, judgments as to whether, and in what degree, the agentdeservesmoral praise or blame for acting as he did. This question as to what is deserving of moral praise or blame is, I think, often confused with the question as to what is right or wrong. It is very natural, at first sight, to assume that to call an action morally praiseworthy is the same thing as to say that it is right, and to call it morally blameworthy the same thing as to say that it is wrong. But yet a very little reflection suffices to show that the two things are certainly distinct. When we say that an actiondeservespraise or blame, we imply that it isrightto praise or blame it; that is to say, we are making a judgmentnotabout the rightness of the original action, but about the rightness of the further action which we should take, if we praised or blamed it. And these two judgments are certainly not identical; nor is there any reason to think that what is rightalwaysalso deserves to be praised, and what is wrongalwaysalso deserves to be blamed. Even, therefore, if the motiveisrelevant to the question whether an action deserves praise or blame, it by no means follows that it isalsorelevant to the question whether it is right or wrong. And there is some reason to think that the motiveisrelevant to judgments of the former kind: that we reallyoughtsometimes to praise an action done from a bad motive less than if it had been done from a good one, and to blame an action done from a good motive less than if it had been done from a bad one. For one of the considerations upon which the question whether it is right to blame an action depends, is that our blame may tend to prevent the agent from doing similar wrong actions in future; and obviously, if the agent only acted wrongly from a motive which is not likely to lead him wrong in the future, there is less need to try to deter him by blame than if he had acted from a motive which was likely to lead him to act wrongly again. This is, I think, a very real reason why wesometimesought to blame a man less when he does wrong from a good motive. But I do not mean to say that the question whether a man deserves moral praise or blame, or the degree to which he deserves it, dependsentirelyoralwaysupon his motive. I think it certainly does not. My point is only that thisquestiondoessometimesdepend on the motive in some degree; whereas the question whether his action was right or wrongneverdepends on it at all.(Ch. 5 ?16)

There are, therefore, at least three different kinds of moral judgments, in making which it is at least plausible to hold that we ought to take account of motives; and if all these judgments are carefully distinguished from that particular kind which is solely concerned with the question whether an action is right or wrong, there ceases, I think, to be any reason to suppose that this last question ever depends upon the motive at all. At all events the mere fact that motives are and ought to be taken account of insomemoral judgments does not constitute such a reason. And hence this fact cannot be urged as an objection to the view that right and wrong depend solely on consequences.(Ch. 5 ?17)

But there remains one last objection to this view, which is, I am inclined to think, the most serious of all. This is an objection which will be urged by people who strongly maintain that right and wrong donotdepend either upon the nature of the action or upon its motive, and who will even go so far as to admit as self-evident the hypothetical proposition thatifany being absolutelyknewthat one action would have better total consequences than another, then itwouldalways be his duty to choose the former rather than the latter. But what such people would point out is that this hypothetical case is hardly ever, if ever, realised among us men. We hardly ever, if ever,know for certainwhich among the courses open to uswillproduce the best consequences. Some accident, which we could not possibly have forseen, may always falsify the most careful calculations, and make an action, which we had every reason to think would have the best results,actuallyhave worse ones than some alternative would have had. Suppose, then, that a man has taken all possible care to assure himself that a given course will be the best, and has adopted it for that reason, but that owing to some subsequent event, which he could not possibly have forseen, it turns outnotto be the best: are we for that reason to say that his action was wrong? It may seem outrageous to say so; and yet this is what we must say, if we are to hold that right and wrong depend upon theactualconsequences. Or suppose that a man has deliberately chosen a course, which he has every reason to suppose willnotproduce the best consequences, but that some unforseen accident defeats his purpose and makes it actually turn out to be the best: are we to say that such a man, because of this unforseen accident, has acted rightly? This also may seem an outrageous thing to say; and yet we must say it, if we are to hold that right and wrong depend upon theactualconsequences. For these reasons many people are strongly inclined to hold that they donotdepend upon theactualconsequences, but only upon those which were antecedentlyprobable, or which the agent hadreasonto expect, or which it waspossiblefor him toforsee. They are inclined to say that an action isalwaysright, whatever itsactualconsequences may be, provided the agent had reason to expect that they would be the best possible; andalwayswrong, if he had reason to expect that they would not.(Ch. 5 ?18)

This, I think, is the most serious objection to the view that right and wrong depend upon theactualconsequences. But yet I am inclined to think that even this objection can be got over by reference to the distinction between what is right or wrong, on the one hand, and what is morally praiseworthy or blameworthy on the other. What we should naturally say of a man whose action turns out badly owing to some unforseen accident when he had every reason to expect that it would turn out well, is not that his action was right, but rather thathe is not to blame. And it may be fully admitted that in such a case he reallyoughtnot to be blamed; since blame cannot possibly serve any good purpose, and would be likely to do harm. But, even if we admit that he was not to blame, is that any reason for asserting also that he acted rightly? I cannot see that it is; and therefore I am inclined to think that in all such cases the man really did actwrongly, although he is not to blame, and although, perhaps, he even deserves praise for acting as he did.(Ch. 5 ?19)

But the same difficulty may be put in another form, in which there may seem an even stronger case against the view that right and wrong depend on theactualconsequences. Instead of considering what judgment we ought to pass on an actionafterit has been done, and when many of its results are already known, let us consider what judgment we ought to pass on itbeforehand, and when the question is which among several courses still open to a man heoughtto choose. It is admitted that he cannotknow for certainbeforehand which of them will actually have the best results; but let us suppose that he has every reason to think that one of them will produce decidedly better results than any of the others梩hat all probability is in favour of this view. Can we not say, in such a case, that he absolutelyoughtto choose that one? that he will be acting verywronglyif he chooses any other? We certainlyshouldactually say so; and many people may be inclined to think that we should be right in saying so, no matter what the results may subsequently prove to be. There does seem to be a certain paradox in maintaining the opposite: in maintaining that, in such a case, it can possibly be true that heoughtto choose a course, which he has every reason to think willnotbe the best. But yet I am inclined to think that even this difficulty is not fatal to our view. It may be admitted that we should say, and should be justified in saying, that he absolutelyoughtto choose the course, which he has reason to think will be the best. But we may be justified in saying many things, which we do not know to be true, and which in fact are not so, provided that there is a strong probability that they are. And so in this case I do not see why we should not hold, that though we should be justified in saying that heoughtto choose one course, yet it may not be really true that he ought. What certainly will be true is that he will deserve the strongest moral blame if he does not choose the course in question, even though it may be wrong. And we are thus committed to the paradox that a man may really deserve the strongest moral condemnation for choosing an action, whichactuallyis right. But I do not see why we should not accept this paradox.(Ch. 5 ?20)

I conclude, then, that there is no conclusive reason against the view thatour theoryis right, so far as it maintains that the question whether an action is right or wrongalwaysdepends on itsactualconsequences. There seems no sufficient reason for holding either that it depends on the intrinsic nature of the action, or that it depends upon the motive, or even that it depends on theprobableconsequences.(Ch. 5 ?21)




 来源:网络
相关文章
共有评论 0相关评论
发表我的评论
请遵守《互联网电子公告服务管理规定》及中华人民共和国其他有关法律法规。
用户需对自己在使用本站服务过程中的行为承担法律责任。
本站管理员有权保留或删除评论内容。
评论内容只代表网友个人观点,与本网站立场无关。
用户名  密码  验证码 看不清楚,换张图片
0条评论    共1页   当前第1
本类固项
  • “道济”哲学研究网 © 2011 版权所有 All Rights Reserved.
  • 西南民族大学哲学研究院 主办
     
    友情链接 | 联系我们 | 管理入口
     
    地址:成都市一环路南四段 邮编:610041 电话:(028)85522045 85522033
  • 皖ICP备11005164号